r m p |
Theological Publications |
Protestant
Hermeneutical Axiomatics
by Robert M. Price
The Challenge of Exegesis: Expecting the
Unexpected
What is the difference between exegesis and
hermeneutics? They are two phases of biblical interpretation. The first is
descriptive, the second prescriptive. Exegetes strive to reconstruct what really
happened, what the original writer seems to gave wanted the readers to receive.
Exegesis approaches the text as a monument of culture, a window into the soul of
the writer (William Dilthey, Pattern and Meaning in History: Thoughts on
History and Society. Translated by H.P. Rickman. NY: Harper & Row, 1962:
Richard E. Palmer, Hermeneutics:Interpretation Theory in Schleiermacher,
Dilthey, Heidegger, and Gadamer. Northwestern University Studies in
Phenomenology and Existential Philosophy. Gen. ed. John Wild. Evanson:
Northwestern University Press, 1969). Exegetes seek to discover how the writer
viewed things; what were his or her ruling assumptions? And what did they assert
on the basis of their assumptions?
There is a hermeneutical or exegetical
circle, a back and forth between reader and text: one's questions illumine the
text, make it speak. And yet one soon meets resistance; something does not make
sense. So one begins to revise one's initial assumptions about the text. Once
one adjusts one's lenses in this way, the text starts making more sense. And
this process will no doubt repeat several times. In fact, if it seems too easy
to grasp the import of the ancient writer, one might start wondering whether one
has missed something! Perhaps the greatest danger is eisegesis: reading into the
text what one wants to find there.
This is the danger of "engaged
scholarship." As Kierkegaard said, your faith and its hunger for verification
can cause you to lean too heavily on the saw; a more delicate touch is called
for. You won't be able to see how weak your scriptural evidence is if your
belief preceded your evidence for it! As long as the verses you marshall are
recruits fighting for the "right" cause, you think the battle's won, even if
none of them are armed and half of them are crippled! Most biblical apologetics
partake of this weakness, leaving outsiders to question the honesty or even the
sanity of believers who offer such arguments.
To be honest, one must be ready to see
what one doesn't want to see in the evidence. The mindset and beliefs of people
in the past may seem quite alien to us, and that is why it is difficult to be
sure we have read the ancient authors rightly. What their words suggest to us at
first reading may have meant something quite different to them.
Albert Schweitzer (The Mystery of the
Kingdom of God; The Quest of the Historical Jesus) chronicled the
long scholarly endeavor to penetrate the dogmatic screen of the Gospels, to sift
through the evidence, and to delineate the outlines of the historical Jesus, the
real Nazarene who lived among men and women, not the stain-glass figure of
Christian theology. The result always seemed to be a Jesus tailor-made to play
the figurehead for the modern, liberal agendas of the scholars who did the
reconstructions! They had made Jesus over, not in the image of Christian dogma,
true, but in their own images. And this was not because of any crafty scheme to
employ Jesus as a poster boy for their favorite causes. No, they did their best.
The problem was that they proved unable to listen for the truly other.
All they could see or hear was what seemed plausible, what made sense, to them.
This is what modern literary critics call our tendency to "naturalize" the text,
to reduce the strangeness of a text to something we can more readily understand
on our own terms.
And so a first-century religious radical
remained invisible to the questers after the historical Jesus. Schweitzer
somehow managed to set aside his own criteria of verisimilitude and likely
motivation, opening himself to the Other. And what he heard was the voice of a
man whom we would readily call a fanatic: a proclaimer of the imminent end of
the world who believed God had sentenced him to die in order to force the slowly
grinding wheel of history into motion. This Jesus, Schweitzer realized, would
prove an embarrassment to modern religion which had expected to find a congenial
Jesus who would vindicate their own more enlightened perspective.
Or think of Vincent Bugliosi, the
prosecutor in charge of the Charles Manson case. Bugliosi was certain Charlie
had masterminded the series of grisly deaths, but he found it difficult
establishing any credible motive. It was only once he began to suspect that
Manson was operating from altogether different assumptions than he or the jury
or most people would, that he began to piece the case together. He had to
outline the delusional apocalyptic scenario which had prompted Manson's horrific
deeds. He had staged the killings to look like a race hate crime so as to fan
into flame the apocalyptic war of Helter Skelter, Armageddon. Working from
conventional, familiar, sane assumptions got Bugliosi exactly nowhere. He had to
be open to the Other. The problem, the challenge was well put by Mr. Spock as he
explained to Captain Kirk why he had hitherto not been able to detect the source
of some malignant radiation. It was unfamiliar; their sensors had not been built
with this force in mind. And thus the scanner could pick up only what it had
been built to scan for. How to widen the scanning capabilities? That's the task
of the historical imagination.
The Challenge of Hermeneutics: Bridging the
Ages
Hermeneutics is quite a different matter, a
matter of what the ancient text means, or how it applies, now, whereas exegesis
strives for the author's intent, i.e., what it meant then, to them, in their
circumstances. In other words, can we draw a lesson from what the author meant,
either directly or obliquely? The task of hermeneutics presupposes a distance
between reader and text, ruling out, at least some of the time, direct
application. So great is this challenge, so wide the gap to be covered, that one
should not so blithely assume it is even possible. Islamic theologians reject
the very possibility of epistles counting as Scripture, since they are directed
from one human being to another. The problem is not so much that an epistolary
author could not be inspired by Allah; rather, it is the particularity of the
intended readership. How dare we read someone else's mail (for example, the
Corinthians') and assume any of it pertains to us?
The distance may be due to cultural or
philosophical differences, differences between our theological perspective and
those of the ancient writers. When we demythologize what the ancients took
literally, we have quite a ditch to jump, but hardly less of one when we try
merely to systematize their utterances, quipped on this or that occasion. This
latter is why we have such differences between Calvinism and Arminianism, for
example, since both are attempts to do something the biblical authors never did:
to work the various biblical statements on divine providence and grace into a
coherent abstract system.
Or, it may be a set of new questions,
such as medical ethics or nuclear war, arising since the scriptures were
written, which set the distance hermeneutics seeks to span. When certain
contemporary issues, such as abortion, are simply not mentioned in scripture,
all one can do is to infer general principles from cases that are mentioned in
scripture, and then speculatively apply such principles. Anti-abortionists say
that the Bible condemns abortion. How is that possible when the Bible never
mentions the issue? Because these folk are jumping the gun, failing to draw the
vital distinction between what the text actually does say ("Thou shalt do no
murder") and what they infer from it ("abortion would seem to be a sub-type of
murder"). And they fail to recognize that no inference can be certain.
None of this is really new. All these
challenges, pretty much, were faced by the ancient interpreters of even more
ancient texts including the Torah and the Iliad. The techniques fashioned to do
the job, including allegory, reasoning from analogous cases, etc., were already
the stock in trade of the Jewish rabbis and the Stoic philosophers. I am
concerned in this essay to identify some major points of tension in a particular
stream of hermeneutics, namely Protestant hermeneutics. This approach
represented a something of a new departure in the days of Luther and Calvin, and
now the approach has fallen on rough times. Once new and revolutionary,
Protestant hermeneutics now seem superannuated and even obsolete. We shall see
why.
Protestant Axiomatics of Scripture
Protestant hermeneutics are based on Martin
Luther's paradigm, the first axiom of which is sola scriptura, which
means that scriptural interpretation is logically prior to theology or
tradition. One should get one's beliefs from scripture, and not impose one's
beliefs on it, as Luther's Catholic foes did.
The second axiom asserts the
normativeness of scripture's single, natural, literal sense. It must be read
with the same methods one would use to decipher any other ancient writing. Thus
Luther's espousal of the grammatico-historical method. One does exegesis of the
Bible according to the historical information available on the times and
according to the grammar of the Greek, Hebrew, and Aramaic languages. Just as
one would never look for allegorical and kabbalistic secret meanings smuggled
into Caesar's Gallic Wars by the Holy Spirit, neither should one so
approach the Bible. Inspired though the Bible is, it is an inspired human
writing, to be read by humans as humans read human writings! One needs no divine
X-ray vision to discern what the scriptural authors intended to tell us. Even in
the case of the Revelation of John, one does one's homework familiarizing
oneself with the codes of the literary genre of apocalypses. Even puzzles are to
be taken literally, i.e., strictly according to the known rules for deciphering
them.
The inspiration of scripture is
irrelevant during the process of exegesis. Where it becomes relevant is in the
stage of hermeneutics, where we try to discern our obligation to do what
scripture says.
The third axiom of Protestant
hermeneutics is the Analogy of Scripture. This is to assume the unity and
harmony of the canonical books. If a book violates this "analogy," it is
excluded from the canon. Thus Luther waxed bold to relegate Hebrews, James,
Jude, and Revelation to an appendix to his New Testament canon, because he felt
that they did not comport with the Pauline gospel of salvation by grace through
faith alone. But within the canon, the prevailing maxim shall be that "scripture
interprets scripture," the "less clear by more clear." If, say, Paul is found
seeming to say in one place that people will be saved by performing the works of
the Law (Romans 2:6-7, 13), we are to deem this text "less clear" than those in
which he ("more clearly") says that no one will be saved by legal obedience
(Romans 3::20). The apparent sense of the former may seem clear in its own
right. Its supposed lack of clarity comes from its seeming failure to match up
with the apparent sense of the preferred texts. "Less clear" is thus seen to
mean "apparently clear in meaning, but problematical in implication." The
euphemism of "clarity" (or the lack of it) is, as we shall see, important since
it masks an important equivocation.
The fourth axiom of Luther's paradigm
is the Perspicuity of Scripture. We don't need an infallible interpreter, such
as the Pope, since the infallible scripture is plain in its meaning to all sane,
unprejudiced, and moderately intelligent readers. That may explain why Luther
was scornful of those who disagreed with him: the Pope, Ulrich Zwingli, Kaspar
Schwenkfeld. He couldn't allow himself to believe they could rationally or
sincerely disagree with him.
A House of Cards is Our Mighty Fortress
But, I am sorry to say, these four cardinal
principles of Protestant hermeneutics contradict and devour one another, leaving
biblicists with an incoherent mess. The assumption of the Analogy of Scripture
is possible only insofar as we have already adopted the dogmatic presupposition
of a single Divine Author of all parts of scripture ("plenary inspiration"). And
then one feels one cannot read the Bible simply as any other set of texts. No
one insists, for example, on harmonizing Calvin and Arminius! One does, of
course, seek to iron out seeming contradictions between divergent passages in
the work of a single author (St. Augustine, for example), but one does not
refuse to admit as a last resort that the writer was inconsistent within a
single work or may have changed his mind between one work and the next.
Even biblicists, so-called biblical
literalists (though, as James Barr points out, this is a misnomer, since literal
interpretation is quickly sacrificed to non-literal so long as the latter is
deemed more compatible with the supposed "inerrancy" of the biblical text) will
admit that scripture is filled with "apparent contradictions." Apologist Gleason
Archer has even compiled an Encyclopedia of Biblical Difficulties,
something one would hardly expect to be necessary with a perspicuous inerrant
book, though the irony seems thus far to have escaped Archer and his readers.
Biblicists feel they must deny that the Bible might contain "real" as opposed to
"apparent" contradictions, because if it contained real ones, then biblicism
("The Bible says it; I believe it; that settles it!") would be sunk. If passage
A contradicted passage B, how would poor mortals who would have no beliefs on
revealed matters if we could not derive them from citing an inspired scripture,
know which biblical text to believe and which to reject? Thus it seems better to
hold that the contradiction is merely apparent, that the solution to the puzzle
is merely elusive thus far. Somehow the seemingly clashing contents of both
texts could be shown to agree if we had some extra information. In the meantime
we will just effectively ignore the scripture passage that "apparently
contradicts" the one which contains ideas we want to believe, that our creed or
church tells us to believe. Protestants will readily stake their eternal
salvation of Romans 3:20 and the doctrine of grace into which it neatly fits.
What to do with Romans 2:6-7, 13? Ignore them, or, which is the same thing,
pretend they say what Romans 3:20 says.
How is it possible that biblicists have
not yet grasped that "apparent" contradictions are absolutely fatal to their
doctrine of "biblical authority," based as it is on the "plain sense of the
text"? Remember, it is none other than the plain, straightforward, apparent
sense of the text that is authoritative for Protestants, that is, if we are to
stick with grammatico-historical exegesis and so fend off mischievous Papistical
allegorizing. That is what grammatico-historical exegesis
means: the
apparent meaning. Luther framed this principle precisely in order to
rule out Catholic claims to have dug up some non-apparent "real" meaning of the
text. And yet it is just such a stratagem to which inerrantists constantly
repair with all their talk of "apparent contradictions"! They are defending
inerrancy in the same way medieval Catholics defended the sale of indulgences!
Only in their case, the irony is all the greater since the appeal to esoteric
meanings of scripture to defend desirable doctrines is an implicit repudiation
of the very hermeneutic on which all their other doctrinal beliefs rest!
If one doubts the truth of this, just
look at the practical results of the "apparent contradiction" or "more
clear/less clear" subterfuge: is not even the biblicist left deciding whether he
will accept verse A (e.g., Romans 2:6-7, 13) as normative for faith and
harmonize verse B (e.g., Romans 3:20) into pretended conformity with it? Of the
other way around? Is Romans 3:20 to be seized on as the true teaching of God's
Word, and Romans 2:6-7, 13 subordinated to it? This is exactly the same
arbitrary procedure they fear would result if they were to admit that scripture
"really" contradicts itself. The sole difference is whether one wants to
admit one is setting aside the passage whose plain meaning one does not
like.
But is the choice arbitrary? In
one sense yes, since one might equally have chosen either. In another sense, the
choice is anything but arbitrary: it will be dictated by the needs of one's
preferred or inherited theology. There is nothing arbitrary about that. Thus
Walter Kaufmann mocked that you can predict how a theologian will "gerrymander"
the Bible as soon as you know what denominational label the theologian bears!
And then what we are saying is that our doctrine is prior to our biblical
exegesis and controls it before we ever even open the Bible. And that is the
Roman Catholic view. Moreover, the claim for the perspicuity of Scripture is
demonstrably false, as witness the conflict of interpretations. Even if there
were no contradictions or patent errors in scripture, the simple fact of
ambiguity is enough to rule out "confident preaching of God's authoritative
Word" as ridiculous and megalomaniacal.
Is There a "Plain Sense"?
Perhaps the problem in all this is the very
notion that there is such a thing as the plain sense of the text, an unadorned,
objective meaning that ought to be obvious to any unprejudiced reader. What if
there just is no plain meaning, whether that of a doctrine one wants to embrace
or that of a contradiction one would prefer to ignore?
With Stanley Fish (Self-Consuming
Artifacts; Is There a Text in This Class?: The Authority of Interpretive
Communities; Doing What Comes Naturally), guru of Reader Response
criticism, we must recognize that we belong to self-contained "communities of
interpreters," sharing with our fellow members a set of assumptions as to what
kind of thing to look for in texts, what methodology to use, and even what
results we can expect. We are ultimately reading the text through a lens,
feeding the text through a grinder of our own choosing. It will seem to us,
secure within this "plausibility structure" (Peter L. Berger and Thomas Luckmann,
The Social Construction of Reality), that we are merely seeking the
"plain sense" of the text, but it will seem so only because we naively take for
granted a previously controversial reading that our community of interpreters
has long ago come to take for granted. For medieval Catholics, some allegorical
or anagogical reading that seems preposterous to us today seemed entirely
natural, even inevitable. To them, Martin Luther's "truncated" reading of the "grammatico-historical"
sense of the text seemed as crazy as it would seem to us if someone urged us to
take the parables as straight historical anecdotes with no deeper meaning.
Scripture is in the eye of the beholder. This subjectivity is hidden
from us by the fact that both our exegetical colleagues and opponents (the only
ones we are close enough to, to argue with!) hold the same basic rules and
assumptions we do. Within that common frame of mind we can have variations on a
theme, but other communities of interpreters are forever sealed off from us. We
are playing baseball; they are playing soccer. We can't play on the same field,
much less win a victory over each other.
This is what Tertullian had in mind
when, in his Prescription against Heretics, he warned the faithful never
to engage Gnostic opponents in scriptural argument. They might win! Therefore
one must rule out the heretics' appeal to scripture a priori. The scriptures
belong to us, not to you! Justin Martyr pursued the same course in his
Dialogue with Trypho. He tried to demonstrate how Jesus fulfilled Old
Testament prophecies - provided, of course, that one approached them from a
Christian perspective! "According to your scriptures, or rather our scriptures,
since they are no longer yours but ours ..."
The Only Assured Result...
With Paul de Man, one of the chief theorists
of Deconstruction, we must come to accept a more modest result from our
exegetical labors. No one can ever achieve an "assured result" in biblical
study. We can understand a text better and better, but we can never be sure that
what looks good to us now will not be overturned by subsequent scholarship,
whether our own or that of others. The "truth" of the passage, however we may
define it, is ever deferred, always postponed. It is a will-o'-the-wisp that
enchants us, leads us on a merry chase, but one with no finish line. The truth
of the text is like a North Star for exegesis: one navigates by it, but one can
hardly hope ever to reach it! Only a fool thinks he has. We can never boast of
having arrived at a correct, definitive "reading" of the text, but only of "misreadings"
that are more or less productive of new insights into the text. The prefix "mis"
serves to remind us that our exegetical suggestions, while plausible, can never
be proven.
Jacques Derrida, the other great
Deconstructionist, poses the problem for traditional interpretation a bit
differently. Derrida believes that we can often be sure enough that we have
discerned what the author of a text intended to tell us, but that we may equally
be able to discern within that text a "countersignature," a meaning at variance
with the intended one. It will have been set loose by the very fact of the use
of language itself, which always ricochets with surprising echoes unintended and
uncontrollable by the author. Every utterance, every written sentence, is a
stone dropped into a pool, and there is no telling how far the ripples will
spread. Eventually they will collide with the banks of the pond and start to
retrace their course, crossing with the ripples that are still on their way
outward.
An example would be the Parable of the
Sheep and the Goats in Matthew 25. Matthew present us with two groups, one whose
behavior we are to emulate, the other whose actions we are to avoid. The Sheep
took every opportunity to assist the downtrodden, altogether oblivious of the
fact that they were serving the incognito Son of Man. Their compassion had been
spontaneous, disinterested, and so their true motives were revealed. The Goats,
presented with the same opportunities, had shown as little humanitarian concern
as Dives had for Lazarus. They protest upon learning that the whole thing was a
sting operation, that the street bum they kicked aside was really the Son of
Man. No fair!, they cry. Why, had they realized it was the Son of Man, in other
words, had they known what was at stake, they would have helped quicker than you
can say "asbestos!" But that's the whole point, don't you see? We can only tell
what your real motives are if you don't know what's at stake! So... why
is Matthew telling his readers what is at stake when they have the opportunity
to help the downtrodden? He has not only rendered the whole scenario futile; he
has also urged his readers to have the same self-seeking motives as the Goats!
This cannot have been his purpose, admittedly. But he had unleashed a
counter-message which utterly confuted his intended message. Which of these is
"the message" of the text?
Even when texts do not present us with
such paradoxes, there is the matter of whether to trust the teller or the tale.
Modern literary theorists, from the New Critics on, have insisted that the
author is but one more reader of the text he/she has written. The text, once
down on paper, speaks for itself. Once it leaves the hand of the author, the
author becomes irrelevant. Traditional scriptural hermeneutics occasionally came
close to recognizing this point, as for instance when Warfield and Hodge
contended that the biblical writers may have had all manner of erroneous
opinions in common with their pre-scientific contemporaries, but that God had
kept such things out of the text. The writers had been simple conduits for the
production of texts.
Postmortem Hermeneutics
When traditional Christian hermeneutics said
God was really the author of the Bible, not so much Paul, Matthew, Isaiah, et.
al., it was surprisingly close to Roland Barthes when he spoke of "the death of
the author," that is, his disappearance from the equation. To say that "God" is
the author of Scripture is tantamount to saying that no one is the author of
scripture, as when an insurance policy calls a random event of destruction "an
act of God." No one caused it. Or when Origen said "God only knows who wrote the
Epistle to the Hebrews," he meant "Nobody knows who wrote Hebrews." We tend to
make the same mistake Odysseus tricked the Cyclops into making: "No man is
killing me!"
A rabbinic tale tells how, at Javneh,
when the rabbis were debating all sorts of halakhic technicalities, Rabbi
Eliezer stubbornly held to his view in the teeth of united opposition from all
the other sages present. He called the river outside to attest his view, hoping
to silence opposition by resort to miracle. Sure enough, the river changed its
course in support of his opinion. But the sages ruled out such a prodigy as
irrelevant. Not to be so easily routed, Eliezer then called the tree outside to
back him up, which it did by uprooting itself. When this marvel, too, was judged
beside the point, Eliezer called the wall of the house of study to witness. It
leaned inward, though out of respect for the other sages, it did not collapse.
Again, inadmissable. Finally Eliezer called on God, whose Voice shook the
rafters, pronouncing agreement with Eliezer's opinion. But even God's opinion
was ruled out! Why? The chief rabbi pointed out that ever since God had caused
Moses to commit the Law to writing, the prerogative of interpreting it has
rested with human beings! God's is but one more opinion! God replies with mock
dismay, "My children have defeated me!"
But one hardly need delve into the
mysteries of Deconstruction to see how facile all the talk of Scriptural
perspicuity and plain sense is; comparing several commentaries on a single text
will demonstrate it readily enough. Once I read, back to back, and in their
entirety, no less than seven commentaries on Romans and was startled to find
major disagreements on every hand - and this among critical scholars ostensibly
sharing the same methodology! There was little agreement even on points so major
as whether or not Paul believed the Torah was still binding on the Christian
conscience!
We can make the same point starting
from Thomas S. Kuhn's work on the evolution of science via the succession of
paradigms rather than via discoveries of new evidence (The Structure of
Scientific Revolutions). A paradigm refers to a conceptual model, a
theoretical construct applied provisionally to the same old data. One has the
same set of dots before one; they haven't changed. But one tries a new way to
connect the dots using fewer lines than the previous player. This is how
Copernicus' paradigm of heliocentricity replaced Ptolemy's paradigm of
geocentricity. A new theory gets off the ground by proposing a paradigm that
would explain anomalous data that the older paradigm could not explain. If the
new paradigm proves more encompassing as well as more economical (fewer
variables, few factors involved), it gradually replaces the old one. In this
way, we can trace, for example, the succession of "historical Jesus" paradigms
proposed by various scholars. He was the Son of God, then a Jewish preacher of
Ethical Monotheism, then a revolutionist, then an apocalyptic doomsayer, then an
existentialist, a Gandhian social radical, a sort of Zen Master, a feminist, a
magician. Same data, new ways of viewing it. Is one of them superior to the
others? Each one does highlight elements left out or downplayed by the others,
but it's hard to declare anyone the winner. It's the same way in science.
Kuhn never wanted to accept the
implications, but Richard Rorty (Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature) and
Paul Feyerabend (Against Method) both explained why it is hard to name a
definitive criterion by which to choose one paradigm over another: each way of
looking at the data carries its own criteria of plausibility and is
incommensurable with all the others. One's choice might be called intuitive,
even aesthetic in nature, since factors like "simplicity" or "economy of
explanation" may have more to do with our minds' tendency to delight in
architectonic symmetry and balance than with any inherent priority these factors
might have.
Rude Hands/Rood Screen
So far I have argued that recent literary
theory makes it impossible for us to claim that we have arrived at the author's
intended meaning in a text, and that even if we could, we would not even be able
to declare the author's meaning the authoritative meaning. But why not save
ourselves the trouble of acquaintance with literary theory? Why not continue in
the old ways od naively assuming that we can telepathically divine the meaning
of Paul or Jesus or Jeremiah, and then thunder forth our own opinions as the
Word of the Lord? We cannot take this route of escape if we are to keep hold on
our Protestant membership cards, for what we would be doing is to make the old
"commonsense" hermeneutics into sacred hermeneutics. We would be shielding the
text of scripture behind a sacred rood-screen to protect it from profane
scrutiny. But the whole point of the grammatico-historical method of Luther was
precisely to lay profane hands on the sacred ark! Luther knew that the moment
one makes the Bible susceptible to privileged means of interpretation, the
mischief will never stop! The Bible will come to mean anything each interpreter
wants it to mean! Today, for us to interpret the Bible as we would any other
text, i.e., any secular text, demands that we apply to it the whole array of
critical approaches in which current literary theory abounds.
In the Beginning Was Logocentrism
The fundamental result of our taking all
these developments in literary analysis seriously, as we must if we still
believe the Bible is amenable to being read like any other book, is that we
simply can no longer thunder forth our own exegetical results as "the Word of
God." We cannot preach "with authority, not as the scribes," since we are no
prophets or messiahs, but merely scribes ourselves! To ramrod home our own
opinions by attributing them to God is the worst kind of manipulation and
priestcraft.
Why not instead follow the lead of
Socrates in our preaching? Why not abandon any appeal to authoritative names and
theological pedigrees? The Bible, as in Jesus' parables, raises questions and
challenges readers to come up with their own answers: "He who has ears to hear
with, let him hear!" Instead of a prophet, dumping the truth like a ten-ton
weight onto our hearers, why not be a Socratic midwife seeking to facilitate the
drawing forth of the truth from within our hearers' own consciences and minds?
That way, it will be their truth in a way a mere quiescent reception of
prepackaged dogma never could be. And that way, it will hardly matter whether or
not the Bible is a credible candidate for a divinely inspired and inerrant book:
one will be able to recognize its truth - wherever it is true - for oneself.
There is no need to appeal to external authority at all. What will be
lost if we do this? What is it we are afraid of? We have shared with traditional
Western philosophy what Derrida calls the Logocentric bias. The proverbs and
stories of the Bible are not good enough for us. We have to abstract them, strip
them down, use them as raw materials to build theological-ethical systems which
we think can alone nourish us. And we seem to thin that ideally every one ought
to believe in the same system, to do and believe the same things. This is why we
speak of "authoritative" preaching in the first place: we want to intimidate
people into conformity with "the Truth." It was quite consistent with this
hermeneutical/homiletical procedure when Reformed Protestant governments
bloodily persecuted Catholic, Anabaptist and Socinian dissenters. Hadn't God
himself dealt with Korah and his buddies pretty much the same way?
Similarly, when we invoke doctrines of
inspiration and debate them vociferously, what is at stake but a far that we
will perhaps lose the secret weapon we love to use to intimidate conformity of
belief. "This is the inspired Word of God; you have no option but to believe
it!" Leaving aside the implicitly coercive strategy of the thing, consider the
whole approach as an example of discredited "foundationalism," the notion that
our most cherished intuitive beliefs ought to be defended by appeal to
supposedly still more basic beliefs. Richard Rorty has exposed the absurdity of
this. Do we really need to "prove" that love is better than hate? It would be
horrifying to think anyone really thought they did! Can you imagine a person who
was prepared to reject love if a better argument could be mounted in a debate on
behalf of hate? So "open" a mind needs to be closed for repairs!
Do we really think anything would be
accomplished if we could demonstrate to the Nazis the untenability of their
position? We can never win a theoretical debate with them, because our
presuppositions and the Nazis' are utterly incommensurable. There is no common
ground between us. Does that mean our confidence in our own values ought to be
shaken? Hell, no! We needn't fear moral paralysis because our deepest
presuppositions are not demonstrable (that's what we mean, after all, by calling
them "presuppositions"!). We just have to decide what we will do about
the Nazis. In Woody Allen's
Manhattan there is a scene at a
cocktail party where Woody's character Ike says "Has anybody read that the Nazis
are gonna march in New Jersey, you know? ... We should go down there, get some
guys together, you know, get some bricks and baseball bats and really explain
things to 'em." An effete martini-sipping liberal counters, "There was this
devastating satirical piece on that on the Op-Ed page of the Times. It
was devastating." Another agrees, "Biting satire is always better than physical
force." Ike stands his ground: "But true physical force is always better with
Nazis, uh... because it's hard to satirize a guy with, uh, shiny boots on."
Exactly. We will have to clash with their beliefs, and with them. We cannot
adjudicate our differences by recourse to some imaginary stock exchange of
theories and opinions.
No Other Foundation
The same ironies crop up with the wrong-headed
foundationalist attempts to secure allegiance to biblical authority by appealing
to a doctrine of inspiration. When you say that we need a doctrine of
inspiration to make scripture authoritative you are denigrating the
contents of scripture. Does you really need some external warrant before you
will take the Sermon on the Mount seriously? Does not deep speak unto deep? And
if the scare-stories of Ananias and Sapphira, Dathan and Abiram, strike you as
no more than superstitious priestcraft, will a claim of inspired authority make
them seem less so? Any doctrine of the plenary inspiration of the Bible flattens
out the whole text so that the tedious minutiae of Leviticus or Chronicles
become no less important than 1 Corinthians 13 or Romans 6-8, and these latter
come to be seen as no more significant than the former.
Such foundationalism leads right back again to Logocentrism: it implies that what is really central to our religious existence is a set of theoretical doctrines, as if salvation and Christian existence were one long process of cramming for a final exam. If one excavates deeply enough, one discovers that the ultimate axioms of Protestant hermeneutics are not Sola Scriptura, perspicuity, the grammatico-historical method, the analogy of Scripture, or even the bearing of Christ to the reader, but rather the notion that there is a single privileged doctrine or set of doctrines to which all others must be subordinated as heretical, and which all human beings must be required to parrot and to obey. It is a set of power relations at bottom. It is not so much as if Jesus should invite whoever is thirsty to come to him and drink; it is more like his counterpart requiring everyone who hungers to take the mark of the number of his name to be eligible for a ration of grain. |
Copyright©2007 by
Robert M Price
Spirit of
Carolina Web Design